Paul Mason
and Armageddon
(Paul Mason:
Postcapitalism Penguin, 2016)
In recent years, a new-ish
breed of capitalism’s critics has arrived. (Apart from Marxists, capitalism has
always had its humanitarian critics, going back to Dickens and beyond.) That
is, those of the newer criticism and of the Keynesian revival since the 2007-08
financial crisis who reject perfect-free-market assumptions about capitalism in
the face of widespread and ever-growing inequality or disproportionality in
income between the world’s richest and poorest.
That is, as both cause and result of what appear to be endless economic
stagnation and portents of crisis which ‘orthodox economics’ seems unable to
solve and indeed ignores altogether. These
critics vary in their attitudes towards socialism. Some of them are entirely
non-socialist, such as Paul Krugman, Will Hutton and Thomas Piketty, while
being critical of capitalism-as-presently-run; some appear to be just that bit more acerbic if
also of the Keynesian oppositional mainstream such as John F Weeks, Mark Blyth
and Ha-Joon Chang with perhaps more leftish social-democratic overtones; and
those like Owen Jones and Paul Mason who are, or pose as, out and out
radical-left and who do not shrink from placing Karl Marx at the centre, or
near the centre, of their critiques, as well as appearing to countenance the removal
of capitalism, perhaps. Taken together,
all of these share either a tacit or overt indignation at our state of affairs
and seek to show, by statistics or persuasion or both, what can be done about
it. The shtick seems right for our febrile and turbulent zeitgeist.
I admired that sentence so much I left it in.
Here is a quote from Paul Mason’s Postcapitalism:
The
tendency of the rate of profit to fall, interacting constantly with the
counter-tendencies, is a much better explanation of what drives the fifty-year
cycle than the one Kondratieff gave. And once you meld the two [Marx and
Kondratieff], long-cycle theory becomes a much more powerful tool than the
Marxist left suspected. (77)
Question: ‘waves’ form no part of Marx’s theory, and if
Kondratrieff’s theory is so patently inferior, why meld them? What is substantively gained by that? This
procedure would appear to be eclectic with a vengeance. But Paul Mason is
nothing if not eclectic .
Postcapitalism, whose title looks so
promising, is vitiated by an attempt to integrate cyclical long-wave (and
long-discredited) theory – initially introduced by A.V. Kondratieff in the
1920s – with Marxist theory as partially grasped. That is, to show why since
2008 (from 1948) we have been in a state of economic and political crisis.
Mason brings in technology, employment and unemployment, investment and
politics as the constituents of fifty-year ‘waves’ of the rise, success,
dominance, decline and depression of capitalism, seen here as coming in
‘cycles’.
Now, cyclical
theory tends to suggest an overall stasis with internal movement and reversal:
as, for example, when we speak of ‘the cycle of the seasons’ of the year. Thus
different periods of the year change but the onward march of years themselves
is eternal and the yearly cycles with varying seasons vary from one another only occasionally. Wave-theory when applied to economics
suggests that business may go up and down in some sort of rhythmic pattern, but
the system in toto goes on forever. Whatever
else it is, wave-theory is certainly not Marxism. Dialectically based, Marxism
suggests that there is qualitative change buried within quantitative change,
such that every now and again, a totality or total situation is suddenly
transformed qualitatively under the increasing pressure of constant and
long-running quantitative change. For example, that after – indeed as a result
of – long years of apparent stability and docility, a society rather suddenly
goes through a revolutionary upheaval that appears to change everything, or a
‘stable’ economic system rather suddenly gives way to a great and terrible
depression: either of these events putting the whole totality upon a
qualitatively new basis. This interpretation, however, is not justified because
historical and economic processes are governed by dialectics but because materialist
dialectical theory is the best mental approximation we have been able to reach
with regard to the dynamics of these phenomena, as being of relatively frequent
occurrence. The former approach would be an example of idealism; the latter is
materialism. The former – without dialectics
or in using idealist dialectics – leads all too easily to the idea that, for
example, it is the waves that control the movement of economic life, like an
ocean wave lending impetus to the water perhaps - not economic life making us think of it in images of coming in waves. What was supposed to have been a
metaphor got out of control by becoming the
thing it previously only expressed poetically, which generally happens when materialist
dialectics as a rational tool is not applied to the formation of theory. This is shown empirically by the fact that
wave-theory cannot, for example, show why ancient slavery evolved into
feudalism, feudalism into early modern capitalism, early modern capitalism into
industrial capitalism, and industrial capitalism into world imperialism.
Wave-theory can attempt to show the rhythms of constant and eternal
quantitative change but is entirely useless at elucidating the nature of the
big qualitative changes in, say,
Western civilisation. This may be why
Paul Mason wishes to inject a bit of Marxism into the mix in order to beef up
the Kondratieff postulates.
Paul Mason
rejects nearly all of the durations of waves suggested by Kondratieff but does
go for the fifty-year wave, since this seems to fit Mason’s own view of the
dynamics involved. But once you pose some sort of ontological reality or ground
for such a thing as a chronologically-rigidified wave, you have to make all the
available data fit into it (not to
speak of the unavailable), rather than formulating theory out of the data. It becomes a kind of secular theology.
One of Mason’s
wave-constituents is science and technology, which indeed feature prominently
in Postcapitalism. But scientific
discovery and technological development do not occur in waves, more specifically in economic waves, if such exist. They
happen regardless of perceived apparent fifty-year cycles. Science and
technology – at varying levels of sophistication, to be sure – come into play
in any period. There was agricultural innovation in the so-called Dark Ages, if
it rather took its time. Indeed, the fact that technologies will tend to
accelerate in progress with their clustering is obviously true but this is not
a process that comes in periodic ‘wave’ form. Technologies are not economic
phenomena; they only become so when they are brought on to the market as
commodities. But even this process conforms to no long-wave pattern in line
with everything else that is contemporaneous. Innovation does not invariably
need a prosperous period full of investment opportunities; it can flourish just
as well in a depression period when (for example) industries desperately
competing over dwindling markets are forced into innovation in order to bump up
their productivity so as to reduce market prices. Depression-hit America in the 1930s was
characterised by enormous industrial invention, renovation and rationalisation,
not to speak of a booming advertising industry as well as a burgeoning and
largescale Art Deco architecture in big cities, small cities and towns all
across the country, meant obviously to be impressive and suggest trendiness.
(The New Deal’s WPA and PWA played a relatively minor part in all this, which
was predominantly commercially-driven.) It is no anomaly that the lavishly
futuristic New York World’s Fair of 1939-40 brought the whole dismal period to
a dazzling climax.
Technological progress has nothing to do with
‘waves’ as such since it happens in all sorts of periods: good years, bad years
and mediocre years. And, for example, it tends to take off in times of war.
(‘War is the mother of invention.’) War
itself rudely upsets the neat patterning of orderly fifty-year waves.
Mason states
that Kondratieff, a Soviet economics professor, fell out of favour with the
Communist Party of the USSR in the 1920s because his wave-theory of capitalism
contradicted Marxism’s dictum of the inevitable downfall of capitalism. But he
entirely distorts the nature of the debate between Kondratieff and the
Bolsheviks. The inevitable downfall of capitalism was never the position of
Marx nor of Lenin or Trotsky. It may have emerged as a heresy within the
Socialist Second International (1889-1914) but Kondratieff was not debating
with the Second International; he faced Lenin and Trotsky. Marxism’s view is
that capitalism will never crumble of its own accord; it can only be brought
down by force, by all who are oppressed and exploited by it. Otherwise
capitalism could go on and on whatever degree of misery it sustained and
extended. The whole point of Marxism
lies in helping working people by giving them an argumentative weaponry with
which to aid them in bringing the system down. So Kondratieff’s seeming
suggestion in his wave-theory that capitalism could go on and on was not the
point at issue as far as Lenin and Trotsky were concerned. What was the point
to them was that Kondratieff’s wave-theory was pure economic metaphysics,
relatively untouched by empirical facts, built only on such facts that appeared
to support the theory. On this account it was ideology, not economic science at
all. And idealist because it suggested
that things are made to happen by mysterious ‘waves’, not of themselves and
their own dynamics in relation to other things within a totality. That
Kondratieff later died in a Siberian concentration camp some time after Stalin
took charge and dispensed with argument altogether is an appalling tragedy:
above all we should honour and memorialise Kondratieff as a martyr to academic
freedom. Mason makes much of this martyrdom but it does not of itself justify
the theory, except perhaps journalistically.
Mason has a
vivid and comprehensive grasp of all that is happening in our present world, as
fully befits one who is so determined on a cause, being also well-informed and
well-travelled. His details are much too profuse to go into here, in any case
because I have little or no quarrel with them as such. What Mason brings to
bear upon that which is engulfing us at the present time seems apparently
sufficient to render the Labour Theory of Value obsolete and so will complete a
massive and global transformation of all present-day capitalism into a ‘post
capitalist’ world by 2075. I will not be around then to tell him he was wrong
and I doubt if he will be around then to hear me. But his argumentation for
change gets woollier as he tries to explain just how all this transition will unfold. Apparently the super-rich 1%
will have to give way, and very rich people will become of the past. The wave,
it seems, is irresistible. And so we have a revolution with no revolution,
which is perhaps why Mason’s ‘visionary bestseller’ (see back cover of Penguin
edition) is extolled from The Guardian to
the Financial Times – a ‘Sunday Times bestseller,’ as the front
cover emblazons. Things change not because of struggle but because we wish it
so. But what about expropriation of the capitalists? What about drones,
robocops and armoured vehicles as likely responses to expropriation? Will the rich simply fall back and say ‘We
were wrong! We were wrong! Take everything we have, for the good of humanity!’
(?) No owning class has ever given up without a fairly good fight. And in any
case the rich have an ‘ultimate weapon’ in their hands: capital. What of
capital in this new future? As long as there is capital, somebody – or indeed
the state – has to own it. Capital is inconceivable without ownership. Whatever
form it takes, it must belong to
someone. You can’t have it in a completely co-operative society because its
essence is accumulation as against – and taken from - the resources and labour of
others. Capital in all its various forms
must be somebody’s property and not somebody else’s, if it is to accumulate as
all capital – to be capital – must. And capital’s surplus value is created from
unpaid labour time. Capital and the labour theory of value are like a horse and
carriage – and about as anachronistic; indeed, as much as any system could be. The
labour theory of value can’t just be wished away. One of the reasons automation
is destroying capitalism, bit by bit, is that it is removing its sole source of
profit in living human labour time which is unpaid. Thus the fewer workers that
are left, the more intensely must they be screwed for the necessary profit,
since automated machines yield only their own value but no new value in commodities. But capital and capitalism have myriad
ways of regaining, maintaining and augmenting profit which they are not about
to dispense with just because the system is becoming unworkable. If capitalism
were to die of its own accord, it would take an awfully long time to expire. The
Roman Empire of the West was almost five hundred years in the declining; had it
not been for the wretched Barbarians it might have gone tottering on for aeons’
longer, with ever-greater misery for its people.
Going back
rather further in time, only an incredibly, astronomically rare event destroyed
the dominating dinosaurs without whose extinction humankind amongst other
beings would never have come into existence.
As with the capital-system called capitalism: nothing is inevitable,
everything is contingent.
Meanwhile, however,
those in power who despaired at trying to bring masses of people towards liking the perpetuation of the system
that exploits them can now rejoice in a book that meets everybody’s needs. For
what we have here, without the forcible expropriation of those who refuse to
give up anything, is a revolution far more utopian than anything Marx could
have dreamt up. As the book does not demand any non-ruling class
instrumentality, let alone the dictatorship of the proletariat, it should continue
to sell.
(With acknowledgements to
Alan Woods, www.marxist.com/marxism-theory-long-waves-kondratieff14100.htm.) (now discontinued)
No comments:
Post a Comment