Thursday, 20 September 2018

'WHAT IF'


‘WHAT IF?’

          Let’s hear it for:
Teleology: Philosophy  the explanation of phenomena by the purpose they serve rather than by postulated causes. (Oxford Concise Dictionary)
          The wittiest example of teleology is Voltaire’s that the nose was created for the spectacles. (Purpose or ultimate function is Aristotle’s  Final Cause for an entity or phenomenon.)
          Respectable historians will thus be somewhat chary of invoking teleology in their explanations of historical phenomena. In fact to many of them ‘teleology’ is a dirty word, not used in public. So they tend to adopt what we could call the proscriptive as opposed to the retrospective approach. That is, start from the beginning of a process and take it from there. This creates certain problems for them. It gets them into difficulties in trying to work out what was and was not of historical significance. What, indeed, is an historical ‘fact’? EH Carr’s What Is History? which remains something of a classic is still recommended to students by way of introducing the whole subject. The book indeed ponders much on all this.
          ‘The prospective interpretation is hopeless because there is no way to show that a shape that is the successor to another is somehow uniquely necessary.’ (JM Fritzman, Hegel, 2014, 45.)
Some histories I have read get so engrossed in impedimenta that they end up explaining away that which is the purported subject. Such as histories of the Industrial Revolution concluding that it sort of never took place. The historian taking this approach is then unable to say why the early 19th century was so very different from the early 18th. The dynamic of history eludes them. Or that the French Revolution was all spectacle and no substance: that is, that many Frenchmen thought there was a revolution but in fact there was not. So, again, why were things different in late 18th-century France from what they had been in the late 17th?   EJ Hobsbawm likens this to a person who says of a desert that it’s not really a desert. There are animal species living in it, as well as plants, some that hold water. So in fact the desert isn’t a desert at all.  Meanwhile crashed aviators have died of thirst in it. These are extreme, but by no means uncommon, instances of wood-for-the-trees thinking. Avoiding the very idea of historical transformation becomes almost obsessional with certain types of conservative pedant. And it is a result of a severely anti-teleological position. One ends up with a history in which it seems nothing really happened at all, except perhaps by accident. This in turn can lead to the despairing view of history as being just a matter of one-damned-thing-after-another: the forlorn belief expressed by the disillusioned liberal historian HAL Fisher in his pre-World-War-II History of Europe. That is, after the Whig Interpretation of History (i.e. ‘progress’) was looking so thin in the 1930s. But opposition to the idea that all history is part of God’s Great Plan doesn’t necessarily require one to think that history is either meaningless or else doesn’t really exist as such, which is where being doctrinally anti-teleological gets you. Which means rejecting Aristotle’s notion of a Final Cause for phenomena entirely. These non-teleological approaches are not without political motive for the preservation of the social status quo; remember Orwell’s Big Brother dictum in Nineteen Eighty-Four: ‘He who controls the past controls the future.’
          Another problem for anti-teleological historians is that human beings, who think and plan and develop strategies and policies, create their own teleologies, and not only conceptually if certain powerful ones  have the ability to put them into actual effect, or in some cases almost or temporarily. We can scarcely leave out the personalities and how they changed things by sheer will of such as Napoleon, or Bismarck, or Hitler, or Lenin etc. There is the history of mass movements of protest showing that teleological purpose works through popular as well as individual will. So purpose enters into the fabric of history, which leads to teleology (which is ‘purpose’) or attempts at one. At the same time the whole scene is littered with setbacks, mistakes and accidents, not to speak (for example) of the possibility that Gavrilo Princip might have missed his Royal targets altogether back in Sarajevo in 1914. For all the actual assassinations there must have been hundreds if not thousands of tries that never came off. So chance seems to play a role as well.
          So are things both global and personal created by necessity or by accident and purely meaningless chance? Or by how much of the former and how much the latter? This makes the whole issue irresolvable. Fortunately, however, we need not worry ourselves unduly over such matters. As the American saying goes, where there’s no solution there’s no problem.
We can go retrospective.
          Julius Caesar crossed the Rubicon. The outcome of this decision was that in time he became Dictator of Rome. And the outcome of that was his assassination, which brought Rome into civil war.
          Caesar might have been killed along the way to Rome if a wheel had fallen off his chariot going downhill. But it didn’t and he wasn’t.
          The decision of advancing upon Rome was a necessary cause in this sequence, while even if there were accidents along the way they too formed part of the outcome.
          It turns out that in the light of the outcome there can be no distinction made between necessities and accidents. In retrospect, everything was necessary.
          The proscriptive approach demands that we continue to ponder now-irrelevant imponderables after they have had their effect. However, the necessity of all the elements can only be identified by the outcome, by what was there at the end: provable by the outcome.
          It was not wholly certain that a significant outcome would have been the result when Caesar started out. His expedition might have ended ingloriously in some swamp or other. Thoughts, actions and serendipidous circumstances are contingent at the time. The fact of the result turns them all into historical actors, making them all necessary in the light of what happened, that is, necessary to the existence of what did happen. This existence, in turn, reaches back to what made it possible, in other words identifies the previously unidentifiable, or alters its previous identity.
          A woman bystander in a crowd of pedestrians being shot at by rampaging terrorists narrowly avoided a bullet while several others around her were shot dead.  By sheer contingency she survived intact. Some years later she gave birth successively to two children. To the children, from their viewpoint as living children, it was absolutely necessary for their mother to have escaped death, necessary for their very existence. But at the time her survival was purely contingent. An action’s  significance can be changed depending on what it ultimately led to. So we view it from the Final Cause, not the First Cause proscriptively. This is where teleology is a vital element, and where it really does not matter whether the vital moments in the lead-up were accidental or necessary.  Prince Arthur’s untimely death was very sad and the nation mourned, but purely by itself it was of little historical importance. Except that it paved the way to the succession of his younger brother Henry VIII – and we all know the various outcomes of that –including not least what amounted to a religious revolution in England! The contingent death of Prince Arthur becomes the necessary death vital in respect of all that subsequently transpired.
          The ‘Cleopatra’s Nose’ theory of history which instances that had her nose been a bit longer she would not have entranced the ageing Caesar and so not won him over, with vast political implications – is whimsically misleading. It seems her nose as well as the rest of her was just right, and so history proceeded accordingly: otherwise it would have turned out differently. And so (according to this account) had her nose been too long there would have been a different history. But there wasn’t, and that’s the point!
 ‘What If’ history is not history. Counterfactual history, hypotheses on what e.g. would have happened if one element or other had been missing, can be useful in understanding what really happened; it is that which the counterfactual historian is driving at, i.e. in emphasising the importance of what was there.
          Artists will be the first to know that serendipity played a major role alongside both purpose and artistic ability in the creation of the final work of art or music or poetry in question. But the work itself is indisputable truth, in the making of which each of these elements had very different facets from one another, but within which all have been turned into a unity that is indissoluble in the resulting work. The outcome determines the natures of all that went into it. Just to pick out one at random, Sibelius was an intermittent alcoholic. When his immortal violin concerto was due for its premiere but was unfinished, a frantic search through the boozers of Helsinki was the only means of locating him and sobering him up sufficiently to put the last touches on the work. He was so drunk when arriving to conduct the premiere of his Sixth Symphony that he stopped the orchestra in the middle of the first movement, thinking it was a rehearsal, and had to be led off the stage. Would Sibelius have been as great if he hadn’t taken to drink? Or would he have been greater? The question is ultimately irrelevant. The work stands, real and unarguably. It puts everything that led up to its realisation in its place.
          Outcomes don’t just happen! They are determined. In the lead-up it didn’t seem possible to fathom all the contingencies that made something happen. Your thoughts and actions count, though, (along with those of your opponents if you have any) because they DO play their part in shaping the outcome. Meanwhile we can do our best to lessen –or make use of – the impact of the accidental.  In any case the outcome, I repeat, does not shape itself.
          In his preface to The Philosophy of Right Hegel wrote: ‘The owl of Minerva [philosophy] spreads its wings only with the falling of the dusk.’ In other words, the understanding of truth is only realised after its object has manifested itself entirely (in the preceding daytime, so to speak). The Final Cause realises itself in revealing the nature and impact of the previous Causes.
         


No comments:

Post a Comment